[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]

Republic of Mali) the International Court of Justice noted that, given
the acceptance of the principle of uti possidetis juris (reliance upon
former colonial administrative boundaries) in the case by both par-
ties it was not necessary to show that the principle was firmly estab-
lished in international law where decolonization was involved.
Nevertheless, the Court insisted that uti possidetis juris is a general
principle of international law which exists to prevent the stability of
new states being endangered by fratricidal struggles, themselves pro-
voked by the challenging of frontiers following the withdrawal of the
administering, colonial power. This is not just an administrative pro-
cedure in Africa but a rule of general scope.1 One might note the
oblique way the issue of self-determination of peoples is side-stepped
by such turns of phrases as that African states have been induced
 judiciously to consent to the respecting of colonial frontiers and
to take account of it in the interpretation of the principle of self-
determination of peoples . . . 2 This is a euphemism for the suppres-
sion of secessionist movements in African states.
This African decision has been applied by Europe s international
lawyers in the context of the break-up of Yugoslavia. The Conference
on Yugoslavia s Arbitration Commission, in its Opinion No. 3
(January 11, 1992), had to answer the question whether the internal
boundaries between Croatia and Serbia and between Bosnia-
Herzegovina and Serbia should be regarded as frontiers in terms of
public international law  a question put by the Republic of Serbia.
The Opinion of the Commission was that once the break-up of
Yugoslavia led to the creation of one or more independent states,
except where otherwise agreed, the former boundaries between
the Yugoslav republics should become frontiers protected by inter-
national law. The principle of respect for the territorial status quo and
M637 CARTY TEXT M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:46 AM Page 80 Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gar
80 Philosophy of International Law
the principle of uti possidetis juris meant that these boundaries were
not to be altered, except by agreements freely concluded. The alter-
ation of existing frontiers or boundaries was not capable of produc-
ing any legal effect.3 Another intimately related question was put by
the Republic of Serbia.
Does the Serbian population of Croatia and Bosnia-Herzegovina,
as one of the constituent peoples of Yugoslavia, have the right to self-
determination? The answer of the Commission, in its Opinion No. 2,
was negative. It held: (1) Not all the implications of self-determination
were clear under contemporary international law. Nevertheless, the
right of self-determination must not involve changes to frontiers at the
time of independence, except by agreement between the states con-
cerned  the principle of uti possidetis juris. (2) Ethnic religious and
language communities within a state had the right to recognition of
their identity under international law. One possible consequence of
this principle might be for the members of the Serbian population in
the two republics to be recognized under agreements between all the
republics as having the nationality of their choice.4
So it appears that the system of international law offers the general
admonition that no claim to self-determination must be allowed to
infringe the principle of territorial integrity of existing states.
However, international law also accepts the imperative that there are
limits to an insistence upon the status quo. Beyond a certain measure
of endurance, people may revolt against discrimination and human
rights and ethnic abuse.5 International law attempts, as well, to insist
on a right of democratic governance as a ground of legitimacy which
states are supposed to accept.6 While all of these considerations
amount to interesting grounds for intellectual reflection and debate,
there is no consistent and reliable institutional theoretical or practical
framework for accommodating these different elements of a possible
legal system.
The subject is made that much more difficult because of the unwill-
ingness of the profession to consider theoretical questions  in this
case, what minimum set of principles and institutions must an inter-
national legal order have to qualify legitimately for the title of legal
order or system? For instance, it is particularly difficult within the dis-
cipline of analytical jurisprudence, which takes its inspiration from
Hart s Concept of Law, to pose effectively the question whether inter-
national law makes up a legal system. It supposes the priority of what-
ever happens to be the dominant (i.e. general or community)
perspective of the chief officials of a legal order as against recalcitrant
M637 CARTY TEXT M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:46 AM Page 81 Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gar
International Legal Personality 81
minorities or dissident members. This community priority is
inevitable given the value skepticism which underlies the analytical
approach. One can only understand obligation from the internal per-
spective of those submitting themselves to it. One can only take lan-
guage at face value, asking how it is actually used in society.7
So, by way of typical illustration, the present editors of
Oppenheim s ninth edition of International Law define international
law, as any other law, in social terms as rules of conduct accepted in
a community by common consent and enforced by an external power
(para. 3). They rely upon the classical distinction between law and
morality (para. 17) in terms of the latter applying to conscience and
the former being enforced by external authority. A clear weakness of
international law, recognized by the editors, is that the enforcement
mechanisms of international law continue to be unsatisfactory and [ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]
  • zanotowane.pl
  • doc.pisz.pl
  • pdf.pisz.pl
  • dudi.htw.pl
  • Linki
    Powered by wordpress | Theme: simpletex | © To, co się robi w łóżku, nigdy nie jest niemoralne, jeśli przyczynia się do utrwalenia miłości.